Thursday, June 6, 2019

Should Christians be Philosophers?

Scripture in Context: Colossians 2:1-3:4

"For I want you to know how great a struggle I have for you and for those at Laodicea and for all who have not seen me face to face, 2 that their hearts may be encouraged, being knit together in love, to reach all the riches of full assurance of understanding and the knowledge of God's mystery, which is Christ, 3 in whom are hidden all the treasures of wisdom and knowledge. 4 I say this in order that no one may delude you with plausible arguments. 5 For though I am absent in body, yet I am with you in spirit, rejoicing to see your good order and the firmness of your faith in Christ.6 Therefore, as you received Christ Jesus the Lord, so walk in him, 7 rooted and built up in him and established in the faith, just as you were taught, abounding in thanksgiving.8 See to it that no one takes you captive by philosophy and empty deceit, according to human tradition, according to the elemental spirits of the world, and not according to Christ. 9 For in him the whole fullness of deity dwells bodily, 10 and you have been filled in him, who is the head of all rule and authority. 11 In him also you were circumcised with a circumcision made without hands, by putting off the body of the flesh, by the circumcision of Christ, 12 having been buried with him in baptism, in which you were also raised with him through faith in the powerful working of God, who raised him from the dead. 13 And you, who were dead in your trespasses and the uncircumcision of your flesh, God made alive together with him, having forgiven us all our trespasses, 14 by canceling the record of debt that stood against us with its legal demands. This he set aside, nailing it to the cross. 15 He disarmed the rulers and authorities and put them to open shame, by triumphing over them in him.16 Therefore let no one pass judgment on you in questions of food and drink, or with regard to a festival or a new moon or a Sabbath. 17 These are a shadow of the things to come, but the substance belongs to Christ. 18 Let no one disqualify you, insisting on asceticism and worship of angels, going on in detail about visions, puffed up without reason by his sensuous mind, 19 and not holding fast to the Head, from whom the whole body, nourished and knit together through its joints and ligaments, grows with a growth that is from God.20 If with Christ you died to the elemental spirits of the world, why, as if you were still alive in the world, do you submit to regulations— 21 “Do not handle, Do not taste, Do not touch” 22 (referring to things that all perish as they are used)—according to human precepts and teachings? 23 These have indeed an appearance of wisdom in promoting self-made religion and asceticism and severity to the body, but they are of no value in stopping the indulgence of the flesh. If then you have been raised with Christ, seek the things that are above, where Christ is, seated at the right hand of God. 2 Set your minds on things that are above, not on things that are on earth. 3 For you have died, and your life is hidden with Christ in God. 4 When Christ who is your life appears, then you also will appear with him in glory."

Lesson Text: Colossians 2:8

Throughout the history of the church philosophy has often been ill-treated in more than one way. Two extremes exist (both of them negative and unbiblical) as it concerns attitudes towards philosophy in relationship to Christianity. Philosophy has at sundry times been overvalued and also undervalued (even despised) in various traditions. The first negative extreme is, as often is the case, what gives rise to the second negative extreme. We are, as frail humans, very given to pendulum swinging, oversteering and landing in opposite ditches. It is indeed the case that both the overestimation of the place of philosophy within the church and the under appreciation of philosophy in the church are errors to be avoided.

One of the principle objections to the study of philosophy among Christians finds its root in a certain understanding of one verse in the new testament, namely our text under consideration, Colossians 2:8.

"See to it that no one takes you captive by philosophy and empty deceit, according to human tradition, according to the elemental spirits of the world, and not according to Christ." 

This verse, the only one in the entire New Testament which actually uses the word “philosophy” (save the use of the term “philosophers” in Acts 17), has stood out in many Christians minds and has predisposed many a believer to be wary of anything bearing the name “philosophy” or “philosophical.” However, to read Colossians 2:8 in such a way as to come away with the belief that all things labeled “philosophy” are to be rejected immediately, dismissed out of hand, is to not read the Scripture here very carefully (which is something we ought always to do).

If we slow down to take a closer look at verse 8 we see that the apostle Paul is not warning believers to avoid all philosophy but, rather, to avoid certain kinds of philosophy. Namely we are to avoid philosophies which are “according to human tradition, according to the elemental spirits of the world, and not according to Christ.” Arguably the apostle Paul may be giving us two different categories of bad philosophy (e.g. 1. Philosophies “according to human tradition” and 2. philosophies “according to the elemental spirits of the world.”), but it seems more probable that he is grouping together all philosophy which is not according to Christ as being “empty” because it is mere “human tradition” as opposed to a philosophy which is informed by revelation. 

It is important to see that the primary distinction Paul is making here is not between two bad philosophies, neither of which are according to Christ, but between bad philosophies and good philosophies. Paul’s wording here in verse 8 is important because by saying “see that no one takes you captive by philosophy… not according to Christ” this strongly suggests that there are philosophies (or at least a philosophy) which is in accordance with Christ. As we will see, the greater context of Colossians 2 will explicate what he means by philosophies not according to Christ.

Before we look at the difference between philosophies not according to Christ and philosophies in keeping with Christ it would probably serve us well to give some definition to the word philosophy itself. As I said earlier the New Testament only employs the word philosophy this one time with the exception of a variation of this word in Acts 17 (philosophy here in Colossians 2:8 and philosophers in Acts 17:18, which is to say those who are practitioners of philosophy. Namely in that context it referred to the Stoics and Epicureans). The word philosophy is itself a composition of two other Greek words, namely, phileo (φιλεω) which means “Ι love” and sophia (σοφια) which means “wisdom.” Hence philosophy is “the love of wisdom.” Upon this definition, insofar as we have a face value meaning for the word philosophy, we must ask ourselves whether philosophy is a bad thing? Should we love wisdom and seek after it or is wisdom a thing to be despised and rejected by Christians?
        
I presume to speak on behalf of all my brothers and sisters in Christ when I say that I am certain whatever form of philosophy we might reject we certainly are not rejecting the most basic notion of philosophy, the love of wisdom. In fact to do so would be very unbiblical of us. Consider the first seven opening verses of the biblical book of Proverbs.

"The proverbs of Solomon, son of David, king of Israel: 2 To know wisdom and instruction, to understand words of insight, 3 to receive instruction in wise dealing, in righteousness, justice, and equity; 4 to give prudence to the simple, knowledge and discretion to the youth— 5 Let the wise hear and increase in learning, and the one who understands obtain guidance, 6 to understand a proverb and a saying, the words of the wise and their riddles. 7 The fear of the Lord is the beginning of knowledge; fools despise wisdom and instruction."

Consider Solomon’s purpose in writing this book, so that the reader may come  “to know wisdom and instruction.” Note further that the Scripture tells us “the fear of the Lord is the beginning of knowledge; fools despise wisdom and instruction.” This really leaves the believer with no room to make the uncareful and blanket statement that “all philosophy is a thing to be avoided.” It is the same kind of uncareful reading of the Colossians 2:8 that leads people to throw around slogans like, “money is the root of all evil” which 1 Timothy 6:10 never actually says.[1] 
        
No, brothers and sisters, we should not despise philosophy because the Lord wants us to love wisdom and pursue knowledge. God does not oppose our growing in intellect or exploring questions about what exists and for what purpose or inquiring into ethical questions, or considering what it means to have knowledge, etc.! Christianity is not an anti-intellectual religion, nor an anti-philosophical religion. Jesus himself, in his human nature, is said to have “increased in wisdom and in stature and in favor with God and man” as he grew up into adulthood.[2]
        
So it is clear from Scripture that philosophy, at its most basic meaning, is not a bad thing. So what of the differences between philosophies “not according to Christ” and philosophy in accordance with Christ? Let us turn back to Colossians 2. Paul has told us that philosophies that are not according to Christ are those that are wrapped up in human tradition and the elemental spirits of this world. Note that “elemental spirits” can also be translated as “elemental principles.” I think, so understood, that both of these descriptions are essentially talking about the same kind of bad philosophy, namely one that operates purely according to human reason and tradition as opposed to philosophy that is done in light of, and under the authority of, divine revelation.
        
But we don’t have to merely speculate as to what Paul means by these two phrases, “human tradition,” and “elemental spirits/principles” because he gives us examples. Immediately after verse 8 (you guessed it, starting in verse 9) Paul tells us “For in Him (that is Christ) the whole fullness of deity dwells bodily, and you have been filled in him, who is the head of all rule and authority.” Herein lies the demarcation between philosophies according to Christ and philosophies not according to Christ. Philosophies which are according to Christ recognize Jesus as the divine and incarnate Son of God who is the head of all rule and authority. Philosophies which start with the proclamation “Jesus is Lord!” and which affirm his coming and headship over all things (e.g. over Logic, Metaphysics, Epistemology, and Ethics, etc.) are welcome philosophies. They have the proper starting point for doing legitimate philosophy, namely, the fear of God. A philosophy which sees the teachings of Christ (and by extension the whole of God’s word) as authoritative and therefore a philosophy which sees itself as subordinate to the rule of Jesus, is a philosophy that is according to Christ. Paul is not condemning this kind of philosophy, rather he is condemning those which do the exact opposite and fail to recognize the rule and authority of Jesus.
        
In verses 11-15 Paul goes on to explain how Jesus has demonstrated his authority over human tradition and reason, and how he has established his rule over the things of this world.

"In him also you were circumcised with a circumcision made without hands, by putting off the body of the flesh, by the circumcision of Christ, 12 having been buried with him in baptism, in which you were also raised with him through faith in the powerful working of God, who raised him from the dead. 13 And you, who were dead in your trespasses and the uncircumcision of your flesh, God made alive together with him, having forgiven us all our trespasses, 14 by canceling the record of debt that stood against us with its legal demands. This he set aside, nailing it to the cross. 15 He disarmed the rulers and authorities and put them to open shame, by triumphing over them in him."

Christ has accomplished salvation for his people, circumcising our hearts, burring us with him in his death by baptism, and raising us to new life in himself by the power of his resurrection. By his power and his work all of our sins are forgiven and our debt is cancelled against God. He has shown his power too, and completely disarmed the rulers and authorities of this world, triumphing over them. Whether Paul here means the human rulers and authorities or the spiritual, demonic forces at work is perhaps a bit ambiguous but it is nonetheless true in both cases. The Jewish authorities, the Roman authorities, and the demonic authorities were all powerless to keep Jesus in his grave and his resurrection proves that he is able to do all he says he can do and that he has saved us from our sins and reconciled us to God! A philosophical starting point which affirms all of this is a philosophy according to Christ.
        
Contrarily it becomes easy to see what kinds of philosophies are not according to Christ. Paul goes on to give us very clear examples in verses 16-23.
"Therefore let no one pass judgment on you in questions of food and drink, or with regard to a festival or a new moon or a Sabbath. 17 These are a shadow of the things to come, but the substance belongs to Christ. 18 Let no one disqualify you, insisting on asceticism and worship of angels, going on in detail about visions, puffed up without reason by his sensuous mind, 19 and not holding fast to the Head, from whom the whole body, nourished and knit together through its joints and ligaments, grows with a growth that is from God. 20 If with Christ you died to the elemental spirits of the world, why, as if you were still alive in the world, do you submit to regulations— 21 “Do not handle, Do not taste, Do not touch” 22 (referring to things that all perish as they are used)—according to human precepts and teachings? 23 These have indeed an appearance of wisdom in promoting self-made religion and asceticism and severity to the body, but they are of no value in stopping the indulgence of the flesh."

Here we see Paul identify certain traditions of men regarding how one ought to eat and drink, or observe certain festivals or the Sabbath. Most likely here he has in mind many of the Pharisaical traditions which Jesus and his disciples constantly butted heads with in the Gospels. It is not that there is no instruction to be had on food and drink or on Sabbath keeping, but man loves to add and subtract from what God has said. Any addition or subtraction to the word of God on these or any other subject is damnable philosophy which leads people away from Christ and toward hell.
        
But it is not just Jewish traditions (rule keeping) and mysticism (such as the worship of angels) that Paul addresses here but also human philosophies like extreme asceticism. The denial of the body of basic needs and even pleasures as was taught by certain Jewish sects (like the Essenes) and Greek philosophers alike (i.e. Stoics and Cynics, etc.). Paul addresses this idea which led people to practice severe treatment of their bodies as if this somehow enabled them a higher degree spirituality or freed them from the power of our flesh. Only Christ can actually free us from the power of the flesh. Denying yourself food and drink and sexuality does not in itself make one spiritual. In fact the spiritual man knows that all of those things have a place in which they may bring glory to God. Any tradition or teaching or practice that loses site of the headship of Jesus is a deceitful and empty philosophy.
        
So philosophies not according to Christ, which is the kind of philosophy condemned by Scripture, are philosophies that do not recognize the true humanity and divinity and Lordship of Jesus Christ. They are philosophies that add and subtract from the teaching of God’s word. They are philosophies that try to use human reason and carnal practices to reach spiritual enlightenment and which fail to acknowledge the rightful rule and authority of Christ.
        
John Calvin sums up these problematic philosophies when he writes:
"He (that is Paul) points out more precisely what kind of philosophy he reproves, and at the same time convicts it of vanity on a twofold account -- because it is not according to Christ, but according to the inclinations of men; and because it consists in the elements of the world. Observe, however, that he places Christ in opposition to the elements of the world, equally as to the traditions of men, by which he intimates, that whatever is hatched in man’s brain is not in accordance with Christ, who has been appointed us by the Father as our sole Teacher, that he might retain us in the simplicity of his gospel."[3]

Philosophies not according to Christ are philosophies that: 1. Do not have an origin point in common with the revelation of God, and 2. Distract people from the simplicity of the gospel. Conversely a philosophy in accordance with Christ will always start with revelation (general or special) and never distract (or detract) from the truth of the gospel (and by extension, any teaching of Scripture).

Now having so far shown that philosophy, the love of wisdom, is a good thing at its most basic level (Proverbs expressly was written to give wisdom to the person who desires it), and having now clearly demarcated the lines between good philosophy (that which recognizes the rule and headship of Jesus and originates from God’s revelation) and bad philosophy (that which which originates in the mind of man and seeks to subjugate revelation to itself and does not recognize the Lordship of Jesus), what should a Christian use philosophy for?

Philosophy is good for Christian use for a great many things. First of all, it is worth mentioning that the modern conception of what philosophy encompases is much narrower than what philosophy was thought to encompass historically. In today’s academy a philosophy major will focus primarily on the study of Logic,[4]  Epistemology,[5] Metaphysics,[6] Ethics,[7] and maybe Aesthetics.[8] These are indeed central philosophical inquiries and they are among the most important questions we can ask. However throughout history, back to the ancient Greeks and through the Medieval era, philosophy also encompassed disciplines like natural philosophy (which we now call “science”)[9] and also mathematics. If you have ever taken any geometry you are interacting with the work of the great philosopher Euclid (who, by the way, would be horrified that we use his philosophy to make physical things because he was just interested in the purity of his axioms and their relationships). Again, philosophy, the love of wisdom, really covers any area of inquiry into any subject matter. To do philosophy is simply to be curious to know and understand.

Broadly speaking, Christians can use philosophy in at least the following two ways:

1. Christians can use philosophy to discover and proclaim truth, goodness, and beauty in the world as revealed to all men by general revelation.

2. Christians can use philosophy to aid in the communication of truths given to us by special revelation.

As to the first Christian use of philosophy (using philosophy to discover and proclaim truth, goodness, and beauty revealed by God in general revelation) this allows us as Christians to study and learn about the world God has made. From the engineering of buildings, cars, planes, etc., to the study of the art of persuasion in speech or exciting story telling in prose, to research into medical technology, to the forms of philosophy we have already discussed that inquire into meaning, truth, goodness, beauty, and knowledge itself, Christians should have a very real interest in all of these forms (and more) of philosophical inquiry. Something is fundamentally broken in the person who is content simply to go through life incurious about the world around him. 

The ancient Greeks were uniquely curious about the world they found themselves in compared to other civilizations. While this did not free the pagan Greeks from their sins, it did lead them into the discovery and advancement of many truths. Much of the math which we use today originated with the Greeks who simply were infatuated with numbers and lines and other objects built into the invisible fabric of the universe and the relationships they had with one another. It was this early natural philosophical inquiry that caused more than just one or two Greeks to begin to wonder if there were not some ultimate God, above all the other so-called gods, that really wove the universe together. The world seemed the product of a great unity of mind rather than a product of a plurality of gods always at war with one another. Thinkers like Plato and Aristotle, among others, actually approached a kind of theism because of their philosophical inquiry.

Paul makes it clear that the reason such truths can be found out by gentiles is because of God’s general revelation in the things he has made. Romans 1:19-20 states, “For what can be known about God is plain to them, because God has shown it to them. For his invisible attributes, namely, his eternal power and divine nature, have been clearly perceived, ever since the creation of the world, in the things that have been made. So they are without excuse.” So clearly did God reveal himself in the natural world to all men that Paul actually acknowledges in Acts 17:24-28 that the Greeks had acquired truth about the one true God. In his message to the Athenian philosophers he states: 

"The God who made the world and everything in it, being Lord of heaven and earth, does not live in temples made by man, 25 nor is he served by human hands, as though he needed anything, since he himself gives to all mankind life and breath and everything. 26 And he made from one man every nation of mankind to live on all the face of the earth, having determined allotted periods and the boundaries of their dwelling place, 27 that they should seek God, and perhaps feel their way toward him and find him. Yet he is actually not far from each one of us, 28 for “‘In him we live and move and have our being’; as even some of your own poets have said, “‘For we are indeed his offspring.’"

Here he is quoting two of their own poet/philosophers and acknowledging that they have rightly inferred certain truths about God from their philosophy even though they have fallen short of actually finding him in a saving way. Nonetheless, truth was discovered and it was discovered because of general revelation. Once again, the only way to do true philosophy is in light of revelation from God and the Greeks at least used general revelation as their starting point and as such discovered many true things but not without a great mixture of error.
        
So what of the pagan philosophers and their works? Are we to commit them to the flames or can we benefit from them? Well, two giants of the faith have taken up sides on this point. One is Tertullian, a late second century Christian teacher who finds no use for the pagans and their philosophy and the other is Augustine who argues there is much which can be redeemed within their work. Let us consider Tertullian’s criticism first.
        
Writing with great passion and concern for his fellow brothers and sister in Christ, as they dealt with constant heresies popping up all around them, Tertullian identified the pagan philosophies and philosophers as a source of much of the trouble. He states:

"These are “the doctrines” of men and “of demons” produced for itching ears of the spirit of this world’s wisdom: this the Lord called “foolishness,” and “chose the foolish things of the world” to confound even philosophy itself. For (philosophy) it is which is the material of the world’s wisdom, the rash interpreter of the nature and the dispensation of God. Indeed heresies are themselves instigated by philosophy. From this source came the Æons, and I know not what infinite forms, and the trinity of man in the system of Valentinus, who was of Plato’s school. From the same source came Marcion’s better god, with all his tranquillity; he came of the Stoics. Then, again, the opinion that the soul dies is held by the Epicureans; while the denial of the restoration of the body is taken from the aggregate school of all the philosophers; also, when matter is made equal to God, then you have the teaching of Zeno; and when any doctrine is alleged touching a god of fire, then Heraclitus comes in. The same subject-matter is discussed over and over again by the heretics and the philosophers; the same arguments are involved. Whence comes evil? Why is it permitted? What is the origin of man? and in what way does he come? Besides the question which Valentinus has very lately proposed—Whence comes God? Which he settles with the answer: From enthymesis and ectroma. Unhappy Aristotle! who invented for these men dialectics, the art of building up and pulling down; an art so evasive in its propositions, so far-fetched in its conjectures, so harsh, in its arguments, so productive of contentions—embarrassing even to itself, retracting everything, and really treating of nothing! Whence spring those “fables and endless genealogies,” and “unprofitable questions,” and “words which spread like a cancer?” From all these, when the apostle would restrain us, he expressly names philosophy as that which he would have us be on our guard against. Writing to the Colossians, he says, “See that no one beguile you through philosophy and vain deceit, after the tradition of men, and contrary to the wisdom of the Holy Ghost.” He had been at Athens, and had in his interviews (with its philosophers) become acquainted with that human wisdom which pretends to know the truth, whilst it only corrupts it, and is itself divided into its own manifold heresies, by the variety of its mutually repugnant sects. What indeed has Athens to do with Jerusalem? What concord is there between the Academy and the Church? what between heretics and Christians? Our instruction comes from “the porch of Solomon,” who had himself taught that “the Lord should be sought in simplicity of heart.” Away with all attempts to produce a mottled Christianity of Stoic, Platonic, and dialectic composition! We want no curious disputation after possessing Christ Jesus, no inquisition after enjoying the gospel! With our faith, we desire no further belief. For this is our palmary faith, that there is nothing which we ought to believe besides."[10]

Tertullian rightly reacts against the errors and heresies produced by those who have wandered far afield into greek philosophy with no grounding in the truths of Scripture. Marcion and the other heretics he mentions were no cute kittens but men twisted and warped by sinful lack of submission to the teachings of Christ, cutting and pasting their Bibles to their own liking and making a god in their own image. It is all too true that the Greek philosophers had a deficient view of God and that those in the visible church who followed those pagan philosophers indiscriminately came to a shipwreck of their faith and of those whom they took down with them. So Tertullian is quite right to strongly oppose the doctrines of demons and false ideas found in the philosophers because of the fruit of death which those ideas bear out. 
        
However, it is possible that Tertullian goes too far in his criticism of Greek philosophy. It may depend on how we understand his final statements. Again, he said, “What indeed has Athens to do with Jerusalem? What concord is there between the Academy and the Church? what between heretics and Christians? Our instruction comes from “the porch of Solomon,” who had himself taught that “the Lord should be sought in simplicity of heart.” Away with all attempts to produce a mottled Christianity of Stoic, Platonic, and dialectic composition! We want no curious disputation after possessing Christ Jesus, no inquisition after enjoying the gospel! With our faith, we desire no further belief. For this is our palmary faith, that there is nothing which we ought to believe besides.”
        
If Tertullian is taken to mean that all things that are not the gospel itself are worthless and we should not hold any interest in them, then I think he goes too far. Surely there are areas of inquiry that are not directly associated with the gospel that are still worth our time. We have already mentioned some of these above. Learning how to do a heart or liver transplant does not have a direct application to the gospel but surely it was a good line of inquiry that led to successfully being able to save lives in this way. Perhaps identifying the nature of knowledge seems to stand apart from the gospel but if we say that we know the gospel and that we know that it is true, what do we mean by that? Surely some of the inroads the Greeks made into the nature of the universe and the things therein have some valuable insights, insights that we benefit from even today. Charitably we may read Tertullian with the lens of Colossians 2 and see that his main concern is the rejection of philosophy that is completely untethered from the gospel and not subordinate to Christ. It would seem however that he is ready to depart from the works of Plato and Aristotle altogether in order to avoid their errors. Augustine, however, offers us a still more excellent way.
        
In his book, On Christian Doctrine, Augustine gives us this helpful illustration of how we ought to think about the truths which pagan philosophers have stumbled upon. He writes:

"Moreover, if those who are called philosophers, and especially the Platonists, have said aught that is true and in harmony with our faith, we are not only not to shrink from it, but to claim it for our own use from those who have unlawful possession of it. For, as the Egyptians had not only the idols and heavy burdens which the people of Israel hated and fled from, but also vessels and ornaments of gold and silver, and garments, which the same people when going out of Egypt appropriated to themselves, designing them for a better use, not doing this on their own authority, but by the command of God, the Egyptians themselves, in their ignorance, providing them with things which they themselves were not making a good use of; in the same way all branches of heathen learning have not only false and superstitious fancies and heavy burdens of unnecessary toil, which every one of us, when going out under the leadership of Christ from the fellowship of the heathen, ought to abhor and avoid; but they contain also liberal instruction which is better adapted to the use of the truth, and some most excellent precepts of morality; and some truths in regard even to the worship of the One God are found among them. Now these are, so to speak, their gold and silver, which they did not create themselves, but dug out of the mines of God’s providence which are everywhere scattered abroad, and are perversely and unlawfully prostituting to the worship of devils. These, therefore, the Christian, when he separates himself in spirit from the miserable fellowship of these men, ought to take away from them, and to devote to their proper use in preaching the gospel. Their garments, also—that is, human institutions such as are adapted to that intercourse with men which is indispensable in this life—we must take and turn to a Christian use."[11]

Here, I think, Augustine offers us a better way to think about engaging non-Christian thinkers. In fact, I think what Augustine suggests is exactly what we see Paul doing in Acts 17 when he quotes two of the Greek poets. Fundamentally we should recognize that if anything is true, if anything is good, if anything is beautiful, it rightly belongs to the Lord. Non-Christians, due to general revelation and God’s common grace to all mankind, have often discovered incredibly true, good, and beautiful things. Very often they use these things to some errant end but that does not negate the truths they have found. The Christian philosopher has the duty to excavate those truths, to plunder the Egyptians, and repurpose them to the glory of God. The Christian philosopher recognizes that any truth that is discovered is a revealed truth, is God’s truth, and it flows from him and should point back to him. Many Christians, like Tertullian, are a bit too quick to throw the baby out with the bathwater. We should follow Augustine’s approach, and Paul’s before him, in isolating the good discovered by non-believers and appropriating it to be used for its truest end, the glory of God.
        
So then, the first purpose of philosophy for Christians is to identify truth, goodness, and beauty in the world (general revelation) and to learn about God through the things he has made, to do good to others with the things we learn, and glorify him. We can also use this as a point of contact with our non-Christian neighbors, taking truths they already recognize and building a bridge for them back to God. We should recognize truth, wherever it is found, is God’s truth.

As to the second Christian use of philosophy (using philosophy to aid in the communication of truths given to us by special revelation) this is where philosophy can become distinctly Christian. This form of philosophy starts with Christian presuppositions revealed to us directly by special revelation (i.e. Scripture). In other words, this where we do philosophy about things that non-Christians would not pursue. Or, in some cases, we use philosophy to make a case for the truth of distinctly Christian doctrines. A primary example is the doctrine of the Trinity. God is one being (or essence) in three persons. A uniquely Christian doctrine that is found in the pages of Scripture by means of three clearly taught truths. 1. There is but one true God. 2. The Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit are distinct persons. 3. The Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit are all the one true God. These three doctrines are clearly taught in Scripture but the word Trinity is not found in the text of Scripture. Nor is there anywhere that explicitly states, “God is one being in three persons.” Christian thinkers, who knew God’s word exceptionally well but who were also well schooled in philosophical inquiry carefully delineated how we ought to talk about God as both one and also three without there being a contradiction in God’s nature. 

One need only read the Athanasian Creed to see how carefully the words were chosen to avoid heresy and uphold orthodoxy concerning God. “We worship one God in Trinity and the Trinity in unity, neither confounding the persons nor dividing the essence.” This is but a small selection of the language of that creed but already we see the technical terminology being employed. What is an essence? That’s a philosophical question! One that is informed by the work of Plato and Aristotle among others. So we see that the chasm between theology and philosophy really all but disappears as soon as we start to carefully articulate our Christian doctrines. Learning to think carefully, form good premises, draw proper conclusion and ask the right questions is utterly crucial to such important questions concerning the nature of God and of salvation. We must be philosophers about such things!

Indeed the Westminster divines were philosophers about such things. Consider the definition of God given in WCF 2.1.

"There is but one only, living, and true God, who is infinite in being and perfection, a most pure spirit, invisible, without body, parts, or passions; immutable, immense, eternal, incomprehensible, almighty, most wise, most holy, most free, most absolute; working all things according to the counsel of his own immutable and most righteous will, for his own glory; most loving, gracious, merciful, long-suffering, abundant in goodness and truth, forgiving iniquity, transgression, and sin; the rewarder of them that diligently seek him; and withal, most just, and terrible in his judgments, hating all sin, and who will by no means clear the guilty."

We could spend weeks breaking apart that definition and considering what it means for God to be “infinite” or “eternal” or “without body, parts or passions” or “immutable.” How can God who is eternal interact with beings in time? How can a God who is immutable and impassible interact with his creatures and respond to their prayers? How can a being be a being and have no body at all? These are but a few reasonable questions that emerge from just a few select parts of the definition of God given in the WCF. All of them have good answers, but not always simple ones. They need careful thought applied to each one. 

The fact of the matter is that we hold things as Christians that require careful thought and explanation. Some of our doctrines are challenged regularly by unbelievers (and false believers) and it is at moments like that we must take up Peter’s charge to “be prepared to give an answer to anyone who asks you for a reason for the hope you have within you.”[12] C. S. Lewis has said, “If all the world were Christian, it might not matter if all the world were educated. But a cultural life will exist outside the Church whether it exists inside or not. Good philosophy must exist, if for no other reason, because bad philosophy needs to be answered.”[13] Indeed, he is right. We live in a fallen world which is constantly challenging and subverting the truth of God, exchanging it for a lie. By engaging in philosophy, under the Lordship of Jesus and with a recognition that all truth is revealed by God (whether generally or specially) we can become more effective case makers for Christianity, answer objection and genuine question from non-believers. We can demonstrate that Christianity is consistent, not contrary to reason, and absolutely true.

One of my all time philosophers is Thomas Aquinas and I would like to finish with a word from him about how Christians should think about philosophy. He writes:

"It was necessary for man’s salvation that there should be a knowledge revealed by God, besides the philosophical sciences built up by human reason. First, indeed, because man is directed to God as to an end that surpasses the grasp of his reason: The eye hath not seen, O God, besides Thee, what things Thou hast prepared for them that wait for Thee (Isa. 64:4). But the end must first be known by men who are to direct their thoughts and actions to the end. Hence it was necessary for the salvation of man that certain truths which exceed human reason should be made known to him by divine revelation. Even as regards those truths about God which human reason can discover, it was necessary that man should be taught by a divine revelation, because the truth about God such as reason could discover would only be known by a few, and that after a long time, and with the admixture of many errors. But man’s whole salvation, which is in God, depends upon the knowledge of this truth. Therefore, in order that the salvation of men might be brought about more fitly and more surely, it was necessary that they should be taught divine truths by divine revelation. It was therefore necessary that, besides the philosophical sciences discovered by reason there should be a sacred science obtained through revelation."[14]

Aquinas has a good word here. Philosophy and human reason can truly discover things about God but not so wholly nor so completely as to be sufficient for salvation. Philosophy is a useful tool for discovering truth and for clarifying truth. Ultimately, however, what man needs is a direct word from God about how we might have forgiveness of sins and reconciliation with God. We need the gospel contained in the word of God. 
        
In summary, then, we see that Paul has not condemned philosophy itself, for philosophy is the love of wisdom and Christians are commanded to seek wisdom and fear God as the beginning of wisdom. What Paul condemns are philosophies not according to Christ which means philosophies that do not recognize him as the divine and incarnate Son of God who defeated sin and death in his crucifixion and resurrection for our salvation. Philosophies that start with man as the beginning of wisdom and that draw conclusions contrary to God’s revealed truth are to be rejected. Instead philosophies in accordance with Christ ought to be erected which are subservient to the lordship of Christ and which affirm what God has revealed (generally and specially). Christians can use philosophy to discover truth, goodness, and beauty in the things God has made and direct the attention of the world to a good God who authored all of those things. We can make good things from the truths we discover for the good of our fellow man. We can plunder the Egyptians and reclaim for God what non-Christians have discovered because of God’s common grace. Finally we can build a positive Christian philosophy to carefully articulate doctrine and provide answers to questions and objections to our faith.
        
A Christian pursuit of philosophy is always subservient to revelation. A pagan philosophy always elevates human reason above revelation. This is what Paul warns us against falling prey to in Colossians 2. As Aquinas is famous for saying, “Theology is the queen of the sciences and philosophy is her handmaiden.” May it always be so for Christian philosophers.


Psalm 111:10


The fear of the Lord is the beginning of wisdom; all those who practice it have a good understanding. His praise endures forever!




________________
[1] Indeed 1 Timothy 6:10 actually says, “For the love of money is a root of all kinds of evils. It is through this craving that some have wandered away from the faith and pierced themselves with many pangs. Money is, in itself, often a good thing. Money meets all kinds of genuine needs such as food for hungry bellies, clothes for naked bodies, etc. The love of money, by which the Scripture means a kind of unhealthy infatuation with collecting as much money as possible no matter the means, is what creates many kinds of evil deeds. A person can, however, be a successful businessman with lots of money and not be wicked insofar as they are good stewards of those resources and they see their wealth as means for the kingdom’s end.
[2] Luke 2:52.
[3] Calvin, John. Calvin’s Commentaries, Vol. 21 (Grand Rapid, MI. Baker 2003) 181.
[4] Logic is the study of how to think properly and draw true conclusions from well ordered premises and, hence, undergirds basically all other forms of inquiry.
[5] Epistemology is the study of knowledge, what it means to say that we “know” something (for instance it has been proposed that knowledge is equal to a justified, true, belief). Can we both have knowledge if our proposed ideas are contradictory?
[6] Metaphysics is the study of, or inquiry into, what exists beyond the physical or natural world (e.g. God, angels, human souls, numbers, colors, Forms, etc.).
[7] Ethics is the study of morality and moral decision making. What makes something moral or immoral? What grounds morality? Is morality objective (true for all people equally) or subjective (relative to each individual or family or nation)? What process ought we to use to make a good moral decision?
[8] Aesthetics is the study of beauty. This garners less interest among many modern philosophers than it should, mainly because they don’t believe beauty is an objectively existing thing and this harkens back to their view of metaphysics and their lack of belief in anything non physical.
[9] The word Science comes from the Latin “scientia” which means knowledge. Implicit in the terminology shift from “natural philosophy” to “science” is the notion by post-enlightenment modernists that philosophy does not yield knowledge but the “scientific method” (based upon observation with the natural senses and repetition in a lab) does. Hence discarding “natural philosophy” for “science” is an post-enlightenment slam against the value of traditional philosophy in general. 
[10] Tertullian, The Prescription Against Heretics, Ch. 7. 
[11] Augustine, On Christian Doctrine, in Great Books of the Western World vol. 18. (Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc., 1990), Book 2, Ch. 40.
[12] 1 Peter 3:15
[13] C. S. Lewis, “Learning in War-Time,” in The Weight of Glory and Other Addresses (Orlando, FL: Macmillan, 1980, rev. and exp. ed.), 28.
[14] Aquinas, Thomas. Summa Theologica  in Great Books of the Western World vol. 19. (Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc., 1990), ?. Part 1, Question 1, Whether, besides philosophy, any further doctrine is required?

Saturday, April 15, 2017

ON THE EXISTENCE OF NUMBERS: A CASE FOR FORMS, UNIVERSALS, AND ABSTRACT OBJECTS

Introduction
One of the premier debates of philosophy is on the problem of Universals, sometimes called the problem of Abstract Objects or Platonic Form. Numbers, if indeed they are real things, fall into the category of Abstract Objects. For the uninitiated, a discussion on whether or not numbers, and other so-called abstract objects, exist may seem very odd. I submit among the reasons why such a discussion may seems odd, that not least among them, is the fact that most people would say the answer is obvious. “Of course numbers exist,” they will say “I see them every day and use them every day.” The existence of numbers is seemingly apparent to all people. But, even though it may seem obvious there are those who have raised valid questions about whether such things as numbers have any real existence or whether they are merely conventions of speech for practical purposes and when we say “two” or “three” we do not really refer to anything at all.
It is the purpose of this paper to outline the debate about the problem of numbers as abstract objects, to weigh the arguments of both sides (i.e. the Realist versus the Nominalist positions, each of which have varied levels of adherence) and then to finally to demonstrate the real existence of numbers and, incidentally, other abstract objects as well. I will demonstrate that this question not only has major implications for mathematics and science but also that it has implications that reach beyond to questions of ontology, that is, reality itself and even theology and questions of the nature of God.
Defining Numbers
What kind of thing is a number?
Defining what a number actually is may be more difficult than many would suppose upon first considering the job. Consider any number whatsoever. For instance take the number two. What is the number two? What is the relationship between the number two and the number one, or three, or 10,000? In fact we might be justified in asking, “is the number ‘two’ the same thing as the number ‘2’?” Is the number two tied to any particular representation of that number in numeric or verbal form? If there sits before you a couple of objects, are they a manifestation of twoness? These questions may be easier to ask than to answer.
Bertrand Russell is one who has taken up the matter and attempted to give a definition of a number. In a short essay entitled Definition of Number he argues that many people approach the problem incorrectly. He states, “Many philosophers, when attempting to define number, are really setting to work to define plurality, which is quite a different thing. Number is what is characteristic of numbers, as man is what is characteristic of men. A plurality is not an instance of number, but of some particular number.” In other words, it seems, Russell is asking what the essence of number is. That thing which makes it what it is and without which it ceases to be what it is.
His reference to man or mankind is apropos because it is another philosophical question which has been wrestled with for several millennia, what makes man man? Mankind has been referred to as rational animals, image bearers, and a great many other things in trying to describe the distinction between ourselves and other living things. But there is a sense in which the question “What is man?” is actually very different from the question “What is number?” When it comes to Man we can refer to tangible qualities which at least separate man’s nature from that of other things, both living and inanimate. So even if the ultimate answer to what man is goes deeper than the physical attributes he carries it must be admitted that number does not even have this as a starting point in the discussion.
Let us continue a bit further with Russell’s attempt to define what a number is. Another interesting point he makes in regard to the definition of number is that “we cannot in any case, without a vicious circle, use counting to define numbers, because numbers are used in counting.” In other words we cannot say the number two is simply that which comes after one and before three when counting because this argument commits the fallacy of assuming the premise in our conclusion (i.e. circular reasoning). Furthering this point he writes, “In counting, it is necessary to take the objects counted in a certain order, as first, second, third, etc., but order is not of the essence of number: it is an irrelevant addition, an unnecessary complication from the logical point of view.” In other words a thing, or set of things, can be an instantiation of number without us counting to that number. In fact they could be an instantiation of a number that is beyond our ability to count to while, all the same, truly exemplifying that number.
So given these helpful preliminary remarks about what a number must not be, what does Russell take to be the proper definition of number? He tells us plainly that “A number is anything which is the number of some class.” While this definition may seem circular at first blush we find that it is, in fact, not. As he argues on, “We define ‘the number of a given class’ without using the notion of number in general; therefore we may define number in general in terms of ‘the number of a given class’ without committing any logical error.” In other words a number is that which corresponds to a class of things. The class of all apples sitting on a given table might might instantiate an example of the number seven. Likewise the number of pencils on the table may also instantiate an example of the number seven. In other words these are two different classes of things which instantiate examples of the same number, in this case, seven. Another way of stating this would be to say that both of those classes share the property of sevenness.
I believe this definition is a very good one. One point where I would differ from Russell is on a basic assumption about the possibility of actual infinities, or actual infinite sets of things. In this same essay he writes, “it is to be presumed, for example, that there are an infinite collection of trios in the world, for if this were not the case the total number of things in the world would be finite, which, though possible, seems unlikely.” It seems to me that Russell’s definition of number, based on classes which instantiate examples of that number, is based on his presumption here that there are an actual infinite number of things in the universe. This is where I would raise a contention up against Russell. I will explain my contrary contention momentarily but I want to state that although I think he is wrong on this point, and that his definition stems from his belief about this point, that his definition of number will still stand once I have constructed my counterpoint and placed his definition on a different foundation.
Now let me explain my contention. What is hopefully becoming clear is that numbers are immaterial, they do not extend into space. I think Russell would agree on this point. The way numbers are represented such as “two” or “2” are not in fact the same as the number itself. Numbers are concepts which correspond to a class of things which have that number. Where I disagree with Russell is on the following point, namely, that the number “two” is a discernable idea even apart from an instantiation of twoness such as a couple of spoons or apples before you on a table. In other words, classes of things in the world exemplify number, and numbers are that which correspond to a given class, but numbers are not, strictly speaking, the same as those classes. This is shown to be the case because more than one class can correspond to the same number. So then numbers are properties which classes exhibit but numbers, as real things, are not dependent on the existence of classes of things to exist. Rather numbers are only dependent on classes of things to exhibit their existence. It is entirely feasible that many numbers (perhaps an innumerable amount of numbers, we might say) exist which do not correspond to any actual class of things in the world.
Russell would, I believe, advocate a view called Nominalism. Given his status as an atheist and a philosophical naturalist I think this assumption is fair because Nominalism must be true if all that actually exists is material things. It is for that reason that Russell believes 1) that an infinite number of things exist in the universe and 2) that numbers correspond to actual existing sets of things from one to infinity. Were this not his position he would have to admit that there is a finite number of numbers which seems to be illogical (seeing as no matter how high of a number we name we can always add one more to it). And yet the idea of an actual infinite set (and by actual I mean a set which is exhibited in the natural world) is also logically impossible.
To demonstrate my last claim about the impossibility of an actual infinite set I turn to the work of William Lane Craig. In his book, Reasonable Faith, Craig discusses the Kalam Cosmological Argument for God’s existence and it is in this context that he demonstrates the logical impossibility of an actual infinite set of thing in the natural world. The Kalam Cosmological Argument is as follows:
  1. Whatever begins to exist has a cause.
  2. The universe began to exist.
  3. Therefore, the universe has a cause.
In defense of the second premise of this argument craig demonstrates the logical impossibility of an actual infinite set of things in the world. By extension he argues that if an actual infinite set is impossible then it is impossible for their to be an infinite amount of days that have passed and, therefore, that the universe must have had a definite beginning a finite time ago in the past.
Here is one way by which Craig demonstrates the logical impossibility of an actual infinite set:
[I]magine a hotel with an infinite number of rooms and suppose...that all the rooms are occupied. There is not a single vacant room throughout the entire infinite hotel. Now suppose a new guest shows up, asking for a room. “But of course!” says the proprietor, and he immediately shifts the person in room #1 to room #2, the person in room #2 into room #3, the person in room #3 into room #4, and so on, out to infinity. As a result of these room changes, room #1 now becomes vacant and the new guest gratefully checks in. But remember, before he arrived, all the rooms were already occupied.

Craig continues by giving several other examples of contradictions that can be brought into play using “Hilbert’s Hotel.”
Another example that helps illustrate this point is that of an infinite line of falling dominoes. Imagine the idea that these dominoes have been falling forever without a beginning. If you can imagine that you are doing something rather impressive for it is an inconceivable notion that we might not be able to eventually track down the first domino that fell! Or try another case in which we imagine an infinite line of blue marbles. Now imagine that we paint every other marble red and separate the red marbles from the blue marbles forming two separate lines of marbles. How many blue marbles do we now have? The answer is necessarily a contradiction for this process certainly divided the line of marbles by two which means a reduction of the number of blue marbles by 50% and yet, if the line of marbles is an actual infinite, the line of blue marbles still has an infinite amount of marbles. We have, in this case, not reduced the number of marbles by division but we have doubled it because now we have two infinite lines of marbles. But then, again, there are actually the same amount of marbles as ever there were, an infinite amount.
So if the reasoning of Craig and other thinkers on this issue is correct that an actual infinite set is logically impossible how can it be the case that 1) it is logically necessary that the number of numbers are infinite and also 2) that actual infinite sets exhibiting those numbers are logically impossible? This is the problem that materialists (i.e. Nominalists) face but which is solved by the kind of Realism I am going to advocate, the view that what many philosophers have called “Universals” or “Abstract Objects” actually exist although in an immaterial way and which are not tied of necessity to things in the natural world but which may be exhibited my some things in it.
What is an Abstract Object?
Although I have just alluded to the concept of abstract objects above it will serve to give a more formal definition here. An Abstract Object is a thing which has an immaterial and necessary existence apart from things in the physical world but which may be exhibited or instantiated as a property of the things that exist in the physical world.  I want to draw attention to a few important words in this definition, namely, “immaterial” and also “necessary existence.”
By immaterial I mean a thing which has no tangibility. By way of example colors, laws of logic, thoughts you are thinking right now, and God are all immaterial. Numbers, as we have said, clearly fit in this group. It makes no sense to talk about touching red or holding the laws of logic in your hand, they are not material things. We may rightfully talk about holding a red object, but what we are really saying is that we are holding an object which has the quality of redness. No one has held pure redness in their hands. We might also speak poetically and talk about thoughts “bouncing around in his head.” But here again this is to speak, shall we say, materialmorphically. That is, it is to speak materialistically about the immaterial.
The other key phrase I used was “necessary existence.” Now this gets down to the heart of the matter because it is a claim that says not only do Abstract Objects like colors, numbers, laws of logic, etc., exist but that they do so of necessity. In other words, it could not be the case that they did not exist. Or, once again, there is no possible world in which these abstract objects are not real. The reason for this is because Abstract Objects, at least on a Realist account, belong to the realm of the eternal and are not tied to any specific world. They are more basic than the material world.
Now, admittedly, I have put the cart before the horse a bit. The definition I have given and fleshed out is a Realist definition (as opposed to a Nominalist definition). Various nominalists treat the idea of abstract objects in different ways but for the most part agree that when we speak of these properties that things have we speak of either something concrete belonging to the physical object or, if we speak of them as Universals, we are merely using these terms as useful fictions. In the next section I will consider these three competing views (Realism, and two different forms of Nominalism) and demonstrate the superiority of the Realist view. That being said, before I am done, I will argue for a uniquely Christian view of Realism that will differ in at least one significant way from the Platonist view which is the original Realism.
Are Abstract Objects Real?
The Platonist view
Mortimer J. Adler has said, “Anyone who classifies things or tries to make definitions may be led to wonder whether classifications are entirely verbal and definitions fictions of the mind, or whether things themselves belong together in some real community based upon an inherent sameness or similarity.” Indeed he is correct and this conversation goes as far back (and probably further) as the fifth century B.C. to a man named Socrates whose teaching has been preserved by his student, Plato.
Socrates view of Form is that which we have been calling “Realism.” More often this is referred to a Platonic Form since it is Plato who recorded the words of Socrates and who, it would seem, agrees and taught these same concepts to his own students. Here is one example of Socrates teaching about Form which directly relates to mathematics, and numbers:
You are aware that students of geometry, arithmetic, and the kindred sciences assume the odd and the even and the figures and three kinds of angles and the like in their several branches of science; these are their hypotheses, which they and everybody are supposed to know, and therefore they do not deign to give any account of them either to themselves or others; but they begin with them, and go on until they arrive at last, and in a consistent manner, at their conclusion? Yes, he said, I know. And do you not know also that although they make use of the visible forms and reason about them, they are thinking not of these, but of the ideals which they resemble; not of the figures which they draw, but of the absolute square and the absolute diameter, and so on—the forms which they draw or make, and which have shadows and reflections in water of their own, are converted by them into images, but they are really seeking to behold the things themselves, which can only be seen with the eye of the mind? That is true.

Socrates, in dialog with Glaucon, has demonstrated his view that mathematical representation are simply that, representative of immaterial concepts. Lines drawn on a piece of paper are not the same as the concepts they represent.
To that very point Socrates has the following conversation with a man named Cratylus:
Let us suppose the existence of two objects: one of them shall be Cratylus, and the other the image of Cratylus; and we will suppose, further, that some God makes not only a representation such as a painter would make of your outward form and colour, but also creates an inward organization like yours, having the same warmth and softness; and into this infuses motion, and soul, and mind, such as you have, and in a word copies all your qualities, and places them by you in another form; would you say that this was Cratylus and the image of Cratylus, or that there were two Cratyluses?

Cratylus answers that he would see it as there being two Cratyluses rather than one and an imitation of that one.
Just as it would be absurd to think that there could be two Cratyluses it would also be absurd to think that lines on a page were the same as the things which they were representing. A red brick is likewise not the same as redness, nor is any given brick the same as the Idea of what a brick is. Certainly, also, the idea of a brick preceded the actual making of a brick. Equally certain is that any given brick that is made is not the same as the idea of a brick. So then there is a separation, according to Socrates and Plato between the Form or Idea and the imitation of copy of that idea. Further the Form must be logically prior to the imitation.
One of the most famous passages in all of Plato’s writings is the allegory of the cave. It is also one of the most useful illustrations that Plato gives of his and Socrates’ view of Form. Consider the situation he sets up:
Behold! human beings living in an underground den, which has a mouth open towards the light and reaching all along the den; here they have been from their childhood, and have their legs and necks chained so that they cannot move, and can only see before them, being prevented by the chains from turning round their heads. Above and behind them a fire is blazing at a distance, and between the fire and the prisoners there is a raised way; and you will see, if you look, a low wall built along the way, like the screen which marionette players have in front of them, over which they show the puppets. I see. And do you see, I said, men passing along the wall carrying all sorts of vessels, and statues and figures of animals made of wood and stone and various materials, which appear over the wall? Some of them are talking, others silent. You have shown me a strange image, and they are strange prisoners. Like ourselves, I replied; and they see only their own shadows, or the shadows of one another, which the fire throws on the opposite wall of the cave? True, he said; how could they see anything but the shadows if they were never allowed to move their heads? And of the objects which are being carried in like manner they would only see the shadows? Yes, he said. And if they were able to converse with one another, would they not suppose that they were naming what was actually before them? Very true. And suppose further that the prison had an echo which came from the other side, would they not be sure to fancy when one of the passers-by spoke that the voice which they heard came from the passing shadow? No question, he replied. To them, I said, the truth would be literally nothing but the shadows of the images. That is certain.
This fascinating thought experiment captures the Platonic view of the world we live in. The things which we see with our eyes, feel with our hands, hear with our ears, etc., are all just shadows, imitations, copies of some truer Form of the things we experience in this present life.
For Plato, everything we experience in this world is but a shadow to true Form that exists unchangeably with the gods. Some things are easier to demonstrate this point with, namely, physical objects in the world. As with my above illustration of the brick, the tangible things are the simplest to conceive of the idea of having a perfect Form of which they are imitations. Less easy to grasp are certain properties like colors (e.g. Red that is exemplified by a certain brick). But the fact is that not only bricks but many other objects in the world exemplify Redness. They all participate in this property. But imagine for a moment that all of the red exhibiting things in the universe suddenly ceased to exist in the universe, at this point would red cease to be a thing? It seems obvious that the answer is no because we are still able to conceive of the color red apart from instances of it. But even more challenging in this discussion than Forms of physical objects or even Redness is concepts like truth, goodness and beauty.
We often attribute these qualities to people and to objects in the world, and we believe them to be really meaningful attributions, but what is the good? What is the beautiful? Or as Pilate once asked Jesus, “What is truth?” It must be the case, if these are to be meaningful kinds of statements to make, that there is an objectively existing goodness, and an objectively existing beauty and so on with truth. The apprehension of this truth is difficult, according to Plato, but is essential to understanding the way things really are. Picking up from where we left off in Plato’s Cave, Socrates continues:
And now look again, and see what will naturally follow if the prisoners are released and disabused of their error. At first, when any of them is liberated and compelled suddenly to stand up and turn his neck round and walk and look towards the light, he will suffer sharp pains; the glare will distress him, and he will be unable to see the realities of which in his former state he had seen the shadows; and then conceive some one saying to him, that what he saw before was an illusion, but that now, when he is approaching nearer to being and his eye is turned towards more real existence, he has a clearer vision—what will be his reply? And you may further imagine that his instructor is pointing to the objects as they pass and requiring him to name them—will he not be perplexed? Will he not fancy that the shadows which he formerly saw are truer than the objects which are now shown to him? Far truer. And if he is compelled to look straight at the light, will he not have a pain in his eyes which will make him turn away to take refuge in the objects of vision which he can see, and which he will conceive to be in reality clearer than the things which are now being shown to him? True, he said. And suppose once more, that he is reluctantly dragged up a steep and rugged ascent, and held fast until he is forced into the presence of the sun himself, is he not likely to be pained and irritated? When he approaches the light his eyes will be dazzled, and he will not be able to see anything at all of what are now called realities. Not all in a moment, he said. He will require to grow accustomed to the sight of the upper world. And first he will see the shadows best, next the reflections of men and other objects in the water, and then the objects themselves; then he will gaze upon the light of the moon and the stars and the spangled heaven; and he will see the sky and the stars by night better than the sun or the light of the sun by day? Certainly. Last of all he will be able to see the sun, and not mere reflections of him in the water, but he will see him in his own proper place, and not in another; and he will contemplate him as he is. Certainly. He will then proceed to argue that this is he who gives the season and the years, and is the guardian of all that is in the visible world, and in a certain way the cause of all things which he and his fellows have been accustomed to behold?

Here Socrates describes a truly painful process of coming to see things as they truly are. We are so accustomed to thinking that what we see is the real thing that it is difficult to accept that what we have experienced is, in fact, merely shadows of the real eternal world. But, Socrates tells us, this painful discovery is absolutely essential if we are ever to truly apprehend the good. If Plato’s forms do not exist then “goodness” is nothing more than social convention. However we all know that it is in fact more than that. Self sacrifice for your brother’s well being is good. Giving your life so that many others may live is praiseworthy. These statements are meaningful. Again Plato lets Socrates put this in own words:
This entire allegory, I said, you may now append, dear Glaucon, to the previous argument; the prison-house is the world of sight, the light of the fire is the sun, and you will not misapprehend me if you interpret the journey upwards to be the ascent of the soul into the intellectual world according to my poor belief, which, at your desire, I have expressed—whether rightly or wrongly God knows. But, whether true or false, my opinion is that in the world of knowledge the idea of good appears last of all, and is seen only with an effort; and, when seen, is also inferred to be the universal author of all things beautiful and right, parent of light and of the lord of light in this visible world, and the immediate source of reason and truth in the intellectual; and that this is the power upon which he who would act rationally either in public or private life must have his eye fixed.

Of course many have, since Plato, taken up the notion of Forms. Descartes is one example who, for instance, argues for the objective existence of triangles:
And what I here find to be most important is that I discover in myself an infinitude of ideas of certain things which cannot be esteemed as pure negations, although they may possibly have no existence outside of my thought, and which are not framed by me, although it is within my power either to think or not to think them, but which possess natures which are true and immutable. For example, when I imagine a triangle, although there may nowhere in the world be such a figure outside my thought, or ever have been, there is nevertheless in this figure a certain determinate nature, form, or essence, which is immutable and eternal, which I have not invented, and which in no wise depends on my mind, as appears from the fact that diverse properties of that triangle can be demonstrated, viz. that its three angles are equal to two right angles, that the greatest side is subtended by the greatest angle, and the like, which now, whether I wish it or do not wish it, I recognise very clearly as pertaining to it, although I never thought of the matter at all when I imagined a triangle for the first time, and which therefore cannot be said to have been invented by me.

Descartes demonstrates by his reasoning that the concept of a triangle is no mere convention or something which could be made up by himself, rather it is an objectively existing idea, a concept, which has meaning apart from it even existing in the world or even in his mind.
Much more could, and deserves to be, said about Platonic Form and the concept of Realism which has many representatives over the centuries. For now, however, we will rest with having laid out the concept as the existence of perfect, unchanging, immaterial objects which things in this world either imitate or participate in but are not, themselves, the thing they imitate or participate in. Realism makes things like references to numbers, moral values (i.e. justice, mercy, love), aesthetic judgment and even colors meaningful rather than mere useful fictions or brute material facts.
The Nominalist view
As with the Platonist/Realist view of abstract objects or Forms it should be noted that there are a slew of different views all of which fit under the umbrella of Nominalist theories. The fact that I am only looking at two of them may not do total justice to every nuance of nominalism but with the space permitted it must do for now. The two forms of nominalism I am going to critique are 1) that properties exist in individual concrete objects and have no universal qualities or 2) that properties are spoken of as universals but, in reality, these are useful fictions and they do not exist.
As to properties existing only individual, concrete objects it was not long at all after Plato that this push back against Socrates teachings were challenged. In fact it was Plato’s own student, Aristotle, who rejected the idea of universals with the exception as an abstraction of the human mind. That is to say that Aristotle believed Redness, for example, exists only in direct union with a physical substance. Now, in fairness to Aristotle, he claims that he is not departing from Socrates’ teaching but that he is agreeing with Socrates and it was those who came after him that, in his view, sort of put words in Socrates’ mouth. Aristotle states, “But when Socrates was occupying himself with the excellences of character, and in connexion with them became the first to raise the problem of universal definition… but Socrates did not make the universals or the definitions exist apart: they, however, gave them separate existence, and this was the kind of thing they called Ideas.” But, regardless of whether or not Aristotle is right here that Socrates (and presumably Plato) didn’t actually hold to the separate existence of the Forms/Ideas/Universals, and this is a very debatable point, the doctrine certainly preceded Aristotle and he is objecting to it.
Adler addresses Aristotle’s view of Form when he writes:
Aristotle’s denial of separate existence, or substantiality, to the Ideas or universals stands side by side with his affirmation of the place of forms in the being of substances and the role of universals in the order of knowledge. Furthermore, he limits his denial of the substantiality of Ideas to those Forms which seem to be the archetypes or models of sensible things. Particular physical things—familiar sensible substances, such as the stone, the tree, or the man—are not, in his opinion, imitations of or participations in universal models which exist apart from these things.

For Aristotle there is Form and matter which equal a composite, concrete thing in the world. One cannot have just matter without form, nor can form exist without matter except in imagination of people by abstraction (i.e. imagining red apart from an object it is attached to). There are  many representatives of this view in history including William of Ockham, Francis Bacon and a good deal of contemporary naturalists.
Now consider the second way of looking at universals under a nominalist account, namely, that they are mere conventions of the mind or useful fictions. George Berkeley represents this view as he speaks about numbers in his work Principles of Human Understanding.
That number is entirely the creature of the mind, even though the other qualities be allowed to exist without, will be evident to whoever considers that the same thing bears a different denomination of number as the mind views it with different respects. Thus, the same extension is one, or three, or thirty-six, according as the mind considers it with reference to a yard, a foot, or an inch. Number is so visibly relative, and dependent on men’s understanding, that it is strange to think how anyone should give it an absolute existence without the mind. We say one book, one page, one line, etc.; all these are equally units, though some contain several of the others. And in each instance, it is plain, the unit relates to some particular combination of ideas arbitrarily put together by the mind.

Clearly, in Berkeley’s mind, numbers are not real things. But what does he offer in support of this claim? His argument seems to be that the same thing can be called by more than one number and therefore numbers are arbitrary. But surely this does not follow! In the example given, the measurement known as a yard, he says it can be called “one, or three, or thirty-six” and because of this he concludes that numbers are arbitrary.
Berkeley’s argument might be more plausible if it were the case that the given length in question was one, three, and thirty-six in the exact same way and at the same time (thereby creating a contradiction) but that is not the case. It is perfectly valid to measure the same length by different units and to come up with different answers. How does this in any way suggest that those numbers don’t have an objective meaning? You could tell a man at the lumber yard that you need a 2x4 three feet long, or one yard, or 36 inches and, no matter what unit of measurement you use to communicate with, he will bring you the right length of board. It is just such a fact that shows these numbers are meaningful and that they can be used to communicate with clarity.
Berkeley’s position is, in my view, an extreme one on more than one front as he is of the opinion that no only do forms and universals not exist but that the external world, the world beyond our sense perception, cannot be known to exist either. He states, “In short, if there were external bodies, it is impossible we should ever come to know it; and if there were not, we might have the very same reasons to think there were that we have now.” This is, I believe, the logical extension of nominalism. The rabbit hole that nominalism leads us down takes us to a place where we can have very little conception of any reality.
Pros and Cons of Realism and Nominalism
The strength of Realism is that it is the common sense view or, at least, it is the view we all seem to assume by our speech. We all speak about things as though universals really do exist. When we say things like “Oh, that thing has the color red in it” we are making a very Universal kind of statement. It assumes Red is a thing in itself and that this object we are pointing out is somehow participating in that redness.
Further, If Realism is correct then we speak meaningfully when we call something true, good or beautiful. We all do, of course, think we are really saying something meaningful when we say “that woman is beautiful” or “that sunset is truly beautiful.” Likewise when we say that the person who beat and murdered his wife and children is “evil” we think that means something real and that it is more than just an expression of personal taste. Numbers, likewise, we speak of as real things which certain sets of things exemplify. The strength then of Realism then is that it corresponds with what we perceive to be the case everyday. If Realism is false it is not obviously so.
A strike against Realism might be that it is challenging to prove beyond the fact that we all seem to intuit it to be the case. Given that it refers to an immaterial ultimate reality we do not find it easy to investigate by typical scientific means and it must be a strictly philosophical inquiry. Another objection that has been raised by Christians is the problem of God’s Aseity, the doctrine that God alone is eternal. The Platonic doctrine of Forms suggests that these Forms exists eternally alongside the gods but this cannot hold true if Christianity is true. Therefore many Christians have rejected the concept of Platonic From out of a sense of piety.
The strength of Nominalism is that it accords with a materialist view of the universe. Whereas Realism can only be defended philosophically, Nominalism accords with the scientific evidence. All that we can see, hear, smell, touch, taste, etc., would lead us to believe that Nominalism is the correct view. There is no evidence, of this kind, for Realism and many people seem to think that this is the only evidence that counts when it comes to determining truth.
However, the weakness of this position are, obviously, the strengths of the other position. If the Nominalist position is correct than much of what we believe to be meaningful statements about reality, about things outside the self, are in fact not meaningful at all. Further, even laws of nature (gravity for instance) and laws of logic (law of noncontradiction) are not detectable by the scientific method. Even so, they are usually assumed by those who wield the Scientific method and those in the Nominalist camp in general.
Given the various strengths and weaknesses of each view does little, however, to tell us which view is ultimately the true one. At best it seems to suggest that Nominalism is very difficult to live with in a consistent fashion. It is my argument that the deciding factor between Realism and Nominalism is wrapped up in the question of God’s existence and, specifically, the God of the Bible. If the Christian God exists then a type of Realism must be true and no form of Nominalism can be true.
A Third, Uniquely Christian, View
The pros and cons for each position have been clearly laid out in what has been stated above and neither view is without merit or difficulties. If Realism is to be correct then there are two primary challenges for the Christian. First there is simply the challenge of demonstrating that Realism is true by use of purely philosophic means. Second, assuming the first challenge is met, there is the problem of God’s aseity, his sole eternal existence which is challenged by the Platonic conception of Form. I propose to offer a set of logical arguments that will answer both problems at the same time.
To begin with let us presuppose the existence of the Christian God. We might note that there are many good arguments for existence of God (one has been mentioned earlier in this paper) and that this presupposition is hardly a non-evidenced assumption but one that has been found cogent by many of the brightest minds of history. Since defending the existence of God goes well beyond the scope of this paper, let’s just assume the truth of the proposition “The God of the Bible exists” for the time being. I mean to show you now that if this proposition is true then a type of Realism is necessarily true also and, therefore, Nominalism is false.
I offer the following three logical deductions based on our assumption of the existence of the Christian God:
Deduction one: Demonstrating that what is created exists first in the mind of the creator.

  1. If God creates something it must have existence in his mind logically prior to creation.
  2. God has created things.
  3. Therefore, things exist in the mind of God logically prior to their creation.

Deduction two: Demonstrating the properties exist apart from things that exemplify them.

  1. If a Universal property (such as redness) exists in any instance of a thing it must have existed logically prior in the mind of God which is apart from an instance of a thing.
  2. Properties do exist in instances of things.
  3. Therefore Universal properties exist first in the mind of God apart from any instance of a thing.

Deduction three: Demonstrating that all things that exist apart from God have always existed in the mind of God.

  1. Whatever exists, other than God himself, is a creation of God.
  2. All creations of God exist logically prior in the mind of God.
  3. God does not change.
  4. Therefore, all things that exist have always existed in the mind of God.

I conclude, therefore, from what was demonstrated in the three above deductions that all things that exist apart from God have always existed in the mind of God. Further that properties such as color, or abstract objects such as number, or values such good, true and beautiful, exist eternally in the mind of God apart from things which exemplify those qualities. All of these things, existing in the mind of God from eternity, are what we may call Forms, Universals and Abstract objects, etc.
I believe this argument to be not only logically valid, which is undeniable, but also sound. I am not alone on this point as I have two giants of the faith to appeal to in regard to my given arguments. Aquinas and Augustine both are representative of the view I have just expounded. Consider the words of Thomas Aquinas:
It is necessary to place ideas in the divine mind. For the Greek word Ἰδέαis in Latin Forma. Hence by ideas are understood the forms of things, existing apart from the things themselves. Now the form of anything existing apart from the thing itself can be for one of two ends: either to be the type of that of which it is called the form, or to be the principle of the knowledge of that thing, according as the forms of things knowable are said to be in the knower. In either case we must suppose ideas, as is clear for the following reason. In all things not generated by chance, the form must be the end of any generation whatsoever. But an agent does not act on account of the form except in so far as the likeness of the form is in the agent, as may happen in two ways. For in some agents the form of the thing to be made pre-exists according to its natural being, as in those that act by their nature; as a man generates a man, or fire generates fire. But in other agents (the form of the thing to be made pre-exists) according to intelligible being, as in those that act by the intellect; and thus the likeness of a house pre-exists in the mind of the builder. And this may be called the idea of the house, since the builder intends to build his house like to the form conceived in his mind. As then the world was not made by chance, but by God acting by His intellect, as will appear later, there must exist in the divine mind a form to the likeness of which the world was made. And in this the notion of an idea consists.

Aquinas’ example of the builder of a house necessarily conceiving of the house before he builds it is excellent.
It is important to not here, however, that God is no normal builder. For men come to have ideas that they did not always have but God who is eternal and omniscient does not learn, nor think in a linear process and does not come to have new thoughts or ideas but is in a perfect state of knowledge. This is to say, as I argued in my third deduction, that whatever exists in the mind of God has always existed in the mind of God. The Forms are therefore eternal. But note also that locating Forms in the mind of God does away with the problem of God’s aseity. He alone is eternal, and the Forms are also eternal and there is no contradiction or difficulty in both of these things being true. In this way the Christian conception of God is superior to the Greek pantheon which could not have located the forms in the gods themselves who are subject to change and who are themselves created.
To this point Aquinas also quote Augustine who speaks to the eternality of Forms in the mind of God:
Augustine says, “Ideas are certain principal forms, or permanent and immutable types of things, they themselves not being formed. Thus they are eternal, and existing always in the same manner, as being contained in the divine intelligence. Whilst, however, they themselves neither come into being nor decay, yet we say that in accordance with them everything is formed that can arise or decay, and all that actually does so.”

It would seem then that this is a truly Christian solution to the problem of Form. In fact, given an orthodox view of God’s eternal nature and omniscience it would seem that this position is the undeniably Christian view. It does justice to who God is and yet is provides a sufficient grounding for truth, goodness and beauty. It makes our words meaningful because they refer to concepts that God knows from eternity. Numbers are real objects that are attached to concept of classes of things. God knows the exact amount of things in each class that could be formed and these are what numbers are. Further, back to the dilemma I raised in the first section of this paper, about how can it be both true that numbers are essentially infinite and that an actual infinite set of things cannot exist, is resolved by God as well. God knows not only the actual created things, which are finite, but God knows things which do not actually exist. The idea of an infinity is not incoherent in the mind, we all can conceive of an endless set of things, but it is impossible in the physical world. God knows both what is created and that which is conceptually knowable even if not possible in a world such as our own.

Conclusion
I began this paper by defining numbers with the help of Bertrand Russell who helped us see that number are what correspond to a class of things. We found, however, that Russell had some troubling ideas about the possibility of an infinite set of things in the material world, a supposition that leads to contradictory notions. This view held by Russell seems to stem from his commitment to materialism and the necessity that numbers are infinite, therefore necessitating the need for actual infinite sets. Proving that this cannot be the case we set off to find a remedy to the problem of numbers being infinite and yet there being no actually infinite set of things in the material world. I then brought the discussion to concept of Forms, first introduced by Plato and the ensuing conversation about it between Realists and Nominalist. Both views had troubles of their own but Realism was greatly preferable if one could reconcile the view with Christianity and demonstrate that it was actually true. I then demonstrated that if God exists then a modified type of Realism (which locates the Forms in the eternal changeless mind of God) is necessarily true and Nominalism necessarily false.
Certainly some would charge this inquiry into the existence of Forms as little more than an esoteric pursuit which has little to do with real life. Whereas the discussion may be a little esoteric, in the sense that it is technical, it could not have more practical import than it does. The truth is the discussion about the existence of number is part of a much larger conversation as we have seen. The existence of Forms is really about meaning in the universe. Is everything just a brute fact of natural process without meaning or, alternatively, is everything a mere social convention which is ultimately arbitrary? I argue that if there are no Universals, no Forms, then that is all we are left with, a dilemma between two equally disagreeable options.

Thankfully, as we have seen above, we have not only a third option but we have a truth, tied to the existence of God, that Forms do exist and life is full of meaning. Numbers are real things that God knows. Language has objective meaning because words, no matter what language, refer to concepts that God knows. Beauty and moral values also exist as things God knows. The world makes sense because God exists and is the source of Universals and therefore knowable, communicable truth is possible. If God exists then Forms exist and, consequently, Nominalism is false and should be utterly rejected by all Christians.